Legal Case Summary

Schuette v. BAMN


Date Argued: Tue Oct 15 2013
Case Number: 2014-G-3186
Docket Number: 2602792
Judges:Not available
Duration: 62 minutes
Court Name: Supreme Court

Case Summary

**Case Summary: Schuette v. BAMN, Docket No. 2602792** **Court:** Michigan Supreme Court **Argued:** 2013 **Decided:** 2014 **Citation:** Schuette v. Coalition to Defend Affirmative Action, 572 U.S. 291 (2014) **Background:** The case of Schuette v. BAMN (By Any Means Necessary) arose in the context of a ballot initiative known as Proposal 2, which was passed by Michigan voters in 2006. This initiative amended the Michigan Constitution to prohibit affirmative action programs that give preferential treatment based on race, sex, ethnicity, or national origin in public education, employment, and contracting. The Coalition to Defend Affirmative Action challenged the constitutionality of Proposal 2, arguing that it violated the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. They contended that the proposal discriminated against minorities by making it more challenging to pursue affirmative action policies in public institutions. **Issues:** The primary legal issue before the court was whether the voter-approved ballot initiative unconstitutionally discriminated against minority groups by eliminating affirmative action policies in Michigan's public universities and programs. **Arguments:** - **Petitioners (Schuette):** Advocated that the voters had the right to decide the issue of affirmative action through the democratic process. They argued that Proposal 2 was a legitimate exercise of state sovereignty and did not infringe upon constitutional rights. - **Respondents (BAMN):** Argued that Proposal 2 effectively disadvantaged minority groups by changing the rules in a way that made it more difficult for them to gain access to education and job opportunities. They contended that the initiative was a form of racial discrimination that violated the Equal Protection Clause. **Decision:** The Michigan Supreme Court ultimately upheld the validity of Proposal 2. The court concluded that the voters had the authority to decide the question of affirmative action and that the amendment did not violate the Equal Protection Clause. The court emphasized that the democratic process should govern policy decisions regarding affirmative action rather than judicial intervention. **Impact:** The decision in Schuette v. BAMN reaffirmed the ability of state voters to enact laws that affect affirmative action policies within their jurisdiction. It also highlighted the contentious nature of discussions surrounding race, equality, and educational opportunities in the United States. **Conclusion:** Schuette v. BAMN serves as a significant case in the landscape of affirmative action and voting rights, reinforcing the principle that voters have the power to shape public policy through constitutional amendments and ballot initiatives. The decision sparked widespread debate about the future of affirmative action in Michigan and beyond.

Schuette v. BAMN


Oral Audio Transcript(Beta version)

We'll hear argument next today in case 12-682, should he versus the coalition to defend affirmative action. Mr. Birsch? Thank you, Mr. Chief Justice, and may it please the Court. The issue in this case is whether a Michigan constitutional provision requiring equal treatment violates equal protection, and for two reasons the answer is no. First, unlike the laws that issue in Hunter and Seattle, Section 26 does not repeal an anti-discrimination law. Instead, it repeals preferences, and thus it's an impediment to preferential treatment, not equal treatment. I have nothing to do with an anti-discrimination law. It had to do with a remedy de facto segregation. Why isn't this identical to CF? Justice Sotomayor, it's not identical because of the remedy issue. In Seattle, they were trying to create, in the Court's words,, equal educational opportunity by imposing a remedy that would result in equal treatment. You don't think that the proponents of affirmative action are attempting to do the same thing? One of the bill sponsors here said that this constitutional amendment will bring back desegregation in Michigan, and appears to have done just that. Well, there's two points to that question, and I'll address them both. First on the merits, under grudor, the point of preferences in university admissions cannot be solely the benefit of the minority, because under grudor it's supposed to benefit the campus as a whole through diversity, which we think is a lot of a goal. It's a forward-looking action, not a backward-looking action, to remedy past discrimination. And we know that because under grudor, you can use preferences, whether or not there's de facto or dejury segregation, simply to get the benefit. But with respect to your point about the University of Michigan and what has or has not happened here, two thoughts on that. First, we have the statistics that we discuss in our reply brief, where it's not clear that the diversity on Michigan's campus has gone down. But our main point on that is not those numbers, but the fact that there are other things that the University of Michigan could be doing to achieve diversity in raised neutral ways. For example, we know that- I think it's a lot of the fact that all of those efforts had failed. It's one of the reasons why the- I think it was a law school plan in Michigan was upheld. Well, there's social science evidence that goes both ways, but I want to focus on the University of Michigan, because there's two things that they could be doing right now that would get them closer to the raised neutral goal. The first thing is that they could eliminate alumni preferences. Other schools have done that. They have not. That's certainly one way that tilts the playing field away from underrepresented minorities. The other one, and this is really important, is the focus on social- Always not- I'm not sure if it's not wonderful for minorities that they finally get in, they finally have children, and now you're going to do away for that preference for them. It seems that the game post keeps changing in a few years for minorities. Given the makeup of Michigan's alumni right now, certainly that playing field would be tilt at the other way. The other thing that we press is social economic diversity. And at the University of Michigan, there was a stat in the Wall Street Journal just two days ago that if you measure that by a telegram, the number of students who are eligible for those, at the University of Michigan, the number of students who have telegrams is half what it is at more progressive institutions like Berkeley and the University of Texas at Austin

. So the University of Michigan could be trying harder, but our point isn't to get into a debate about whether preferences are good or bad thing because that's not what this case is about. The question is whether the people of Michigan had the choice through the democratic process to accept this court's invitation in Gruder to try race neutral means. Why are unseattle- I have difficulty distinguishing Seattle. One factual difference is that there was a school board there, a directly elected school board elected for a short term of years. Here's the board of trustees. Is that the distinguishing factor in the case on which a principled distinction could be made? I think it's a distinguishing factor. Kind of sticking with how hard is it under the new political process. I think the chart that we have on page 17 of our reply brief explains that it's really easier to change race-based admissions policies now than it was before section 26. And that's one basis. But I think the more fundamental basis is to say what Seattle is about. And if you indulge me, I'm going to suggest that Seattle could mean one of three things. One of those I think you should clearly reject and then the other two I think are possible interpretations that you could adopt. When Seattle talks about racial classifications, it focuses on laws that have a racial focus. Now right out of the box, equal protection is about people, not about laws. But even more fundamentally, that cannot be the right test. At a minimum, that part of Seattle has to go. Because if you had a race neutral law, like Michigan's equal protection clause, which forbids discrimination on the basis of racer sex, it mirrors the concept of the federal clause, that itself would be subject to strict scrutiny because it has a racial focus. So we know that can't be right and that's respondents position. So that leaves you two other choices. And one would be an incremental change to this political restructuring doctrine. The other would be a more aggressive change. The incremental change would be to interpret racial classification in Seattle as meaning a law that one, repeals an anti-discrimination provision as it did in Hunter and Seattle. And two, removes that issue to a higher level of the decision making process. And because Michigan's law requires equal treatment, it eliminates preferences, not an anti-discrimination law, that would be a way that you could keep Seattle and Hunter as a viable doctrine. I don't see the distinction. Bussing could be viewed and was viewed to benefit only one group. There was a preference for blacks to get into better schools. That's the way the case was pitched. That was its justification and to integrate the society. Affirmative action has the same aim

. We've said that in Fisher. It should be to diversify the population. And so it favors diversity as opposed to segregation. But there's a difference between favoring diversity as an abstract concept on campus, which Bruder clearly allows, and remedying past discrimination, which was the point of the busing in Seattle. And that's why we're really in a post-S Seattle world now because under- But there was no proof that there was any desuring segregation in Seattle. That's correct because at the time of Seattle's decision, we didn't yet have parents involved. And so there wasn't a strict scrutiny test that was being applied to that busing program. And so you didn't have to go as far as you would today if you wanted to uphold that same busing program. But what really ties this case here? We were saying there were three things. One, the first to reject. Yes. It can't be just a racial focus. Okay. And the second was an incremental improvement in the democratic process or democratic responsibility. That was the responsiveness, I guess. Right. That plus repealing an anti-discrimination law. I think that's the narrow way. Third, did you say it? Well, the third way is really to look at racial focus and say that's wrong. And maybe this whole doctrine needs to be re-examined. And the way that you could do that is to look at what Seattle and Hunter are really doing, which is falling right into the Washington V. Davis line of cases. Both of those cases could have been resolved by saying, one, there's a disparate impact. And two, given the facts and circumstances in 1969, Akron, Ohio, in 1982, Seattle, Washington, that there was discriminatory animus based on race. And if you did that, you could reconcile those cases with Washington V. Davis and the entire line of equal protection jurisprudence this Court has used since that time. Now, that was a good claim in this case. It just wasn't decided. It wasn't there a racial animus that the reason for proposition two was to reduce the minority population. The Court of Appeals didn't get to that, but there was such a claim

. There was a claim, but Your Honor, there was also a decision. And the district court was really clear on this. Keep in mind that this was a summary judgment posture. And the district court concluded properly that there wasn't even a question of material disputed fact with respect to intent. This is at pages 317 to 319 of the supplemental appendix petition. And that's because the primary motivation for Section 26 included so many members of the non-discriminatory reasons, including the belief of some in Michigan that preferences are themselves race discrimination. Others that race neutral alternatives is actually a better way to achieve campus diversity that results in better outcomes for underrepresented minority students. Some could believe that the preferences result in mismatch as Justice Townsend. That seems to me a good distinction for Hunter and Moky versus Rightman, which the priests don't talk about. Yes. But not necessarily distinction in Seattle, because Seattle you could argue well there are other methods that are less racially divisive. And I think I'd like to come back to Rightman because that fits into this framework too. But I think if you have any question about what Seattle really meant, the place to look is the later decision in Kaya Hoga Falls. Because in Kaya Hoga, the court specifically mentions, quote, the evil of discriminatory intent present in Seattle. That's at pages 196 to 97 of the opinion. And it also talks about the decision-maker's statements as evidence of discriminatory intent in the Hunter case at page 195. And so I think if you look at Kaya Hoga Falls, it's already done some of the work for you if you're going to take the more conservative route. But I don't see how it is intent. The argument would be any different here. What are the main sponsors of this bill said it was intended to segregate again. The voters in Seattle were not all filled with animus. Some of them just cared about their children not leaving, not having outsiders come in. I mean, there's always voters who have good intent. That's true. And there's always some bad apples too. We don't dispute that point. But here you have a district court holding that there's not even a material question of fact with respect to animus because there are so many reasons that could be advanced. And the first legitimate reason is again about mismatch and about the benefits of racial and Seattle as well. Well, it wasn't the issue of animus that drove Seattle. I think it's much harder in Seattle, your honor

. But to fit right men into this discussion, and what I would consider the more conservative way to deal with Seattle and Hunter, one that would preserve those as a doctrine, is to think about how right men would come out under that test. In right men, of course, you had anti-discrimination laws just like in Hunter at the local level, which were then repealed by a state constitutional amendment. And the political restructuring doctrine had not yet been invented yet. And so what the court did is it relied on the California Supreme Court's finding that there was discriminatory animus in striking down those anti-discrimination laws. I think that if you view Hunter and Seattle similarly as cases where if you repeal an anti-discrimination law as opposed to one that requires equal treatment, that's the narrow way to cabin those cases and ones that a way that would allow those cases to survive yet to distinguish Section 26. At one point that we haven't discussed much is the democratic process. And it's important that I emphasize that obviously the use of race-based and sex-based preferences in college education is certainly one of the most hotly contested issues of our time. And some believe that those preferences are necessary for campus diversity. Others think that they're not necessary and in fact that we would have a much better world if we moved past the discussion about race and instead based it on race-neutral criteria. But you're going to ask you to go back to the very first thing you said because I didn't get your point. The question, what impact has the termination of affirmative action had on Michigan, the enrollment of minorities in the University of Michigan? Do we have any clear picture of that? What effect would the repeal of affirmative action has on it? Yes, Justice Ginsburg, we have a muddy picture. As we explain in our reply brief, the first thing that we have is the actual statistics for the first full year after Section 26 went into effect. This is 2008. And what we find is that the number of underrepresented minorities as part of the entering freshman class at Michigan as a percentage changed very little. It went from about 10 and 3-quarters percent to about 10 and a-quarter percent. Then it gets very difficult to track because following the U.S. Census's lead in 2010, the University of Michigan stopped requiring students to check only a single box to demonstrate what their race or ethnicity was and moved to a multiple check box system. And Justice Sonomaeor, when you see in the amiki briefs that there's been a dramatic drop, for example, in African American students on campus at the University of Michigan, those numbers don't take into account that people who before were forced to check a single box now could be checking multiple boxes. And if you fold in the multiple check box students, the number of underrepresented minorities on campus actually comes out higher. Now we don't know what those numbers are because you could have a student who might be white and Asian and they would not be considered an underrepresented minority and they could be in there. But we know that the numbers are a lot closer than when you just look at single check box. So what do we do? It's an isolated statistics from California. And Amika from California, their attorney general, has shown in another state with a similar proposition as shown the dramatic drop. Well, the statistics in California across the 17 campuses in the University of California system show that today the underrepresented minority percentage is better on 16 out of those 17 campuses. It's not at Berkeley. They haven't gotten there yet, but it's better on the rest. And by going to race neutral criteria, what they discovered was that underrepresented minority students have higher GPAs that they take more technology engineering and math classes and they have a graduation rate that is 20 to 25 percent higher than it was before California's proposition 209. You can see similar effects in Texas in their top 10 percent program before it was modified. And not only did it have those positive impacts, but it actually increased minority performance at socially economically disadvantaged high schools where the students said, hey, if I can only get into the top 10 percent of my class, I can be in the University of Texas at Austin

. And again, we can all agree that diversity on campus is a goal that should be pursued. What the California and Texas experiences have demonstrated is that there are good positive reasons why the voters might want to try to race neutral alternatives. Why is it okay to have taken away, not okay to have taken away the decision to have busing from the local school boards, the people on the ground, but it's okay to take that power away from the people on the ground here, the board of regions who are also elected like the school board was in Seattle. Because as the general population has feelings about many things, but the only decision that they're taking educational decision that they're taking away from the board of regions is this one, affirmative action. Everything else they leave within the elected board of regions. You've put your finger on the full crumb of Respondents Best Argument that only race as a factor alone has been removed. And their argument is exactly backwards because it's not Michigan or Section 26 that single out race, it's the equal protection clause itself. Because Justice Sotomayor, if a student wants to lobby for an alumni preference or a cello preference and put it in the state constitution, strict scrutiny is never applied to that effort. But when you try to get a preference based on race or not based on race in the state constitution, strict scrutiny is always applied. And so it's the equal protection clause which is making a differentiation between race and everything else. And that's why this Court in Crawford, again, decided the same day as Seattle at page 538, recognized, quote, a distinction between state action that discriminates on the basis of race. And state action that addresses in neutral fashion race-related manners. And Section 26 falls into that latter category. You've been asked several questions that referred to the ending or termination of affirmative action. That's not what's an issue here, is it? No. And I'm glad that you brought that up, Chief Justice Roberts, because affirmative action means a lot more than simply the use of race or sex-based preferences in University of Admissions. The Article 1, Section 26 only focuses on this one aspect of University Admissions. Now, another important point to understand is that Section 26 is not all about University Admissions. This is actually a much broader law that applies not just to race and ethnicity, but also to sex and to other factors, and that affects not just universities, but also public contracting and public employment. This was a broad-based law that was primarily motivated by the people of Michigan's decision to move past the day when we're always focused on race, exactly as Bruder invited the states to do. And you can see how that discussion gets mired when you look at some of these statistics that we've been talking about. Is someone who has multiple racial boxes checked more or less diverse than someone who only has one box checked? Is someone who comes from outside the country, say, from Mexico? Has done something much more. You're basically saying, because Fisher and Bruder, we've always applied strict scrutiny. Correct. All right. So, it's essentially a last resort within some reason. But what you're saying, if all those others measures fail, you're by constitutions saying you can't go to the remedy that might work. No, that's not what we're saying. But this amendment is stopping the political process. It's saying the Board of Regents can do everything else in the field of education, except this one

. Well, again, it actually runs the other way because equal protection is what singles out, race-focused measures for strict scrutiny. But what we're saying is, under Gruder, race preferences are barely permissible. It cannot be unconstitutional for the people to choose not to use them anymore, to accept this Court's invitation in Gruder to move past the discussion about race and into a race-neutral future. What would you do with the constitutional amendment that said pro-affirmative action laws and only those require a three-quarter vote of the state legislation? Well, under what we're going to call the Nero-safe hunter and Seattle, something like that would be unconstitutional because it removes an anti-discrimination provision and moves it to a higher level of government. Now, one of the problems with keeping that doctrine is that it could also work the opposite way. Pretend that the political climate in Michigan was turned on its head. And the universities had agreed that they were no longer going to use racer-sex in admissions. And then it was the state electorate, either in the legislature or in the Constitution, which imposed a Gruder plan on everyone. Well, under hunter and Seattle, that would have to go because that law removes an anti-discrimination provision and moves it to the higher level. And so that would be one reason why you might want to take the Washington V. Davis approach and consider whether there's discriminatory, animus-based, un-race. But in either of those cases, I think you can either, you know, pare down the doctrine or get rid of it entirely and distinguish our case from it. But the one point that I want to leave you with today is that the core of respondents' arguments that somehow a racial classification can be any law that has a racial focus cannot be the right test. No matter what, that portion of Seattle and Hunter has to go because equal protection is about protecting individuals, not about protecting laws. And even non-discriminatory race neutral laws that have a racial focus would fall into their racial focus test. You know, the hypothetical we give in our briefs on that besides a state equal protection clause would be the Federal Fair Housing Act because it references race, it has a racial focus in the words of Seattle and Hunter. And it has the ability of preventing anyone from lobbying for preferences based on their race or sex at lower levels of the government, either state or local. So under their theory, the Federal Fair Housing Act would have to be applied under strict scrutiny. And their only response to that in the brief is that while the supremacy clause takes care of that problem, and we all know supremacy doesn't kick in until you first determine that the federal law itself is constitutional, and it wouldn't be under their theory. So what we're asking you to do is eliminate that portion of Hunter and Seattle that suggests that a law's racial focus is the sine a quanon of a political restructuring doctrine test. And to either- Mr. Berk, is not the position that was taken in Seattle to derive from a different view of the equal protection clause. I mean, strict scrutiny was originally put forward as a protection for minority. A protection for minorities against hostile disadvantageous legislation. And so the view then was we used strict scrutiny when the majority is disadvantaged the minority. So you do under the Iranian products view you do focus on race. And you ask, is the minority being disadvantaged? If that were the view, then I suppose we would not be looking at this while the criterion is race. And wherever the disadvantage falls with a majority of minorities is just the same. That wasn't the original idea of when strict scrutiny is appropriate. So if we were faithful to that notion that it is measures to disadvantage the minority they get strict scrutiny

. Two thoughts on that, Justice Ginsburg. First, under grudor, this court made crystal clear that a grudor plan is not about which minority group is being disadvantaged or disadvantaged. It's supposed to benefit the campus as a whole. And to the extent the claim is that preferences benefit certain classes of minorities and not others. For example, it benefits African Americans and Latinos, but not Asians even though they're both discrete and insular underrepresented groups. Then it fails under grudor. It can only be something that benefits everybody. But more fundamentally, going back to your question about the origin of the doctrine, I think it's really important to understand why we have Hunter. Because Hunter remember was decided before Washington V. Davis. And when you look at the face of the law in Akron, Ohio in Hunter, there's nothing in there that would trigger strict scrutiny. And so this court was searching for another way to strike down a law that removed an anti-discrimination provision and made it more difficult to reenact at the higher level of the political process. It needed something to fix that. And our point is you can either construe it to do exactly that. That only anti-discrimination law is being struck down and moved to a higher level can satisfy a political restructuring doctrine. Or you can look at it differently. You can say, now that we've got Washington V. Davis, and we all know what the intent was in Akron, that that is a simpler way to address this problem. And we really don't need the political restructuring doctrine at all anymore. But the reason why we had the doctrine in Hunter is because strict scrutiny did not apply. You said that the district court found it was clear that there was no discriminatory intent, but that wasn't reviewed on appeal. No, it was not. But it wasn't a finding. It was actually more than that. It was at the summary judgment stage. The district court correctly concluded there wasn't even a question of disputed material fact as to whether intent was the primary motivation of the electorate. Unless there are any further questions, I will reserve the balance of my time. Thank you, Council. Mr. Rosenbaum, Mr

. Chief Justice, and may it please the Court, may begin Justice Kennedy with the question you raised, and then come to the question that Chief Justice Roberts raised. To begin, Justice Kennedy, there's no way to distinguish the Seattle case from this case. Nor the Hunter case. Both those cases have to be overruled. Here's why the Seattle case is identical to this case. Both cases involve constitutionally permissible plans, which had as their objective obtaining diversity on campuses. Seattle was a K through 12 case. This case is a higher education case. But in both instances, the objective was to obtain diversity. No constitutional mandate to relieve past discrimination, rather, in fact, as the court said, Seattle Tacoma and Wasco were attempting to deal with the fact of segregation. It's not an accurate description of Seattle. I thought that in Seattle, before the school board adopted the busing plan, the Seattle city was threatened with lawsuits by the Department of Justice, by the Federal Government, and by private plaintiffs, claiming that the previous pupil of assignment plan was unconstitutional, involved the day jury segregation. Isn't that correct? That's correct with respect to at least one of the districts, Justice Alito. But in terms of the program itself, there's no dispute that it was done pursuant to a plan for de facto segregation. Moreover, the question you have to understand is, as to Seattle itself, is it not the case that they were threatened with litigation? Yes, but there had been no finding Justice Alito of the jury segregation. And is it the correct that the district court found that there was a jury segregation? That is not correct. There was no finding whatsoever that there had been a jury segregation and that there was a constitutional imperative to correct that desegregation. It was absolutely identical to the situation. And regarding the accountability, your honor is correct. That in Seattle, what we were dealing with was an elected school board. And here is the Michigan brief says, as the Wayne State brief says, as the court specifically found at pages 326A and 327A of the record. This is a political process in which the regents were elected. Have it all times maintained plenary authority over the admissions process itself. And that there are two things. Number one is it delegated to the faculty. And number two, their election, they're elected only rarely and in staggered terms. There's no question that that's correct, your honor. But the ordinary process itself is a politically accountable process. That's what the district court found when it looked at how the system worked. And then what is the board delegated to the various universities, the authority to develop their own admissions programs? Couldn't alter, I'm sorry

. I'm sorry, they did. And then after several years they decided, you know, we don't like the way it's working. They're adopting too many racial preference programs. We're going to revoke the delegation. Absolutely fine. Why is that any different? Because the difference is that in the Seattle case, in this case and in the hunter case, what's going on is a change from the ordinary political process, which your honor perfectly described. They can change it today. They can go to a affirmative action plan today. Repeal it tomorrow. So if there were a provision in the Michigan Constitution that says the Board of Regents is authorized to enact these programs, in other words, delegated from the people in the Constitution to the Board, and then the people changed the delegation by saying no, it's no longer, we're no longer going to leave that up to the Board. We're going to make the decision ourselves in the Constitution. How is that any different? It's different, Your Honor, because of the racial nature of the decision. Under their theory, under their theory, the people of the state of a state could amend their Constitution, put in the legislature two rooms, one for racial matters, one for all other sorts of matters, and say to any entrant who wants to enter that first room, you may do so. But first you have to pay an exorbitant cover charge, and then you have to mount multiple flights of stairs just to begin the process of enacting constitutionally permissible legislation. Or think about it in the desegregation case. A student comes in. A two students come into the admissions committee. One says, and the admissions committee says, we have one question for you. One question for you since you're here to talk about a legitimate factor in pursuit of diversity. Here's the question. Do you want to talk about your race, your race in the context of other factors? And if the answer is yes, that student is shown the door, told go-rays between $5 and $15 million, repeal prop 2, and then you can come back to make the case. Whereas the student says, no, I've just got another legitimate factor, maybe geography, maybe alumni confections, connections, whatever that is, that person is permitted to make the case. It is a racial distinction. Now, Chief Justice Roberts, you're certainly on to something in terms of, are there race neutral methods to get this done? Of course there are. The state constitution itself could be altered so that a different committee or a different set of individuals could make the decision that they don't like the way the regents are doing it. Or they could do it the old fashioned way, the way that the political cowboy system works, which is to say, we are going to work at these universities. That's how affirmative action involving race happened in the first place. That's at pages 270 to 271A and 282A to 293A. They worked for years to be done. I thought the whole purpose of strict scrutiny was to say that if you want to talk about race, you have a much higher hurdle to climb than if you want to talk about something else

. Now you can argue that strict scrutiny should only apply to minorities and not to students who are not minorities. But I thought the court decided that a long time ago. So I don't know why that's a hard question that you ask about. The student says, I want to talk about race. What if it's a white student who comes in and says, I want to talk about race, I'm white and therefore you should admit me. You should give me preference. The state can't say no, we don't want to hear that. The state can say, we don't want to hear that, whether it comes from a white person, a black person, or whoever. If in fact they are not doing it on a race-specific basis, you're exactly right, of course, about strict scrutiny. And the programs in this case, in TV only programs in this case, that are effective, are those that have past strict scrutiny? I don't understand your answer. Then if the student, one student comes in and says, I want to talk about how well I play the cello. All right, we'll listen to that. I want to come in and talk about why I as a white person should get a preference. You have to listen to that because you're listening to the talk about the cello too. You do your honor when the program has passed the strict scrutiny test that we're talking about. And that's the only sort of program that has an issue in this case. Of course you're correct. If it is a grad type program, if it's unconstitutional, if it's a quota system, you don't have to listen to anybody talk about race. But we are only dealing with constitutionally permissible programs. Why it is impossible to distinguish Seattle. And as far as human about Hunter, page 389 of the Hunter decision is the reason Hunter was decided. It's not a Washington Denver. Well, I'm not sure about that. I understood that the answer you gave to the Chief Justice hypothetical. Maybe I misunderstood the hypothetical. Suppose the Board of Regents have a rule. It's written as a rule that the faculty makes a determination whether they should be affirmative action. Yes. Five and the faculty votes for a further vague. Three years later, the Board of Trustees said, we're abolishing the rule. We're doing that ourselves. Violation? Assuming that the Regents say that's fine. No problem whatsoever. No problem whatsoever. That's the ordinary political process. So the Regents can take it away from the faculty. The Regents have been re-induced. The legislature can take it away from the Regents? Not under the Michigan Constitution because the Michigan. No, no, hypothetical case. Okay. Under who's got the authority here? The legislature can take it away. That's not a problem in a situation where that's part of the ordinary. But then the voters can't take it away. At what point is that your objection takes force? I just don't understand. Where they're going to... Don't understand the declension here. My apologies. For the crescendo, whatever you call them. Both are music to my ears. The point, Justice Kennedy, is that the people of the state have multiple options available to them if they don't like the way the universities are operating. But the one option they don't have is to treat racial matters different from all other matters. The example that you gave... That applies in the Chief Justice's hypothetical or my revision of it as between the Board of Regents and the faculty or between the faculty and the legislators. Exactly. And the problem, the problem that the restructuring process gets at because of the particular concern that this Court has shown with respect to the political process, that the political process itself not become outcome-determinate, that the political process itself be a place where we can air these discussions but not create it in a separate and unequal way to make the decision itself through the process. Why is the faculty administration, faculty decision, any less outcome-determinate than what the voters would say? I think there would be people that might disagree with your empirical assumption

. We're doing that ourselves. Violation? Assuming that the Regents say that's fine. No problem whatsoever. No problem whatsoever. That's the ordinary political process. So the Regents can take it away from the faculty. The Regents have been re-induced. The legislature can take it away from the Regents? Not under the Michigan Constitution because the Michigan. No, no, hypothetical case. Okay. Under who's got the authority here? The legislature can take it away. That's not a problem in a situation where that's part of the ordinary. But then the voters can't take it away. At what point is that your objection takes force? I just don't understand. Where they're going to... Don't understand the declension here. My apologies. For the crescendo, whatever you call them. Both are music to my ears. The point, Justice Kennedy, is that the people of the state have multiple options available to them if they don't like the way the universities are operating. But the one option they don't have is to treat racial matters different from all other matters. The example that you gave... That applies in the Chief Justice's hypothetical or my revision of it as between the Board of Regents and the faculty or between the faculty and the legislators. Exactly. And the problem, the problem that the restructuring process gets at because of the particular concern that this Court has shown with respect to the political process, that the political process itself not become outcome-determinate, that the political process itself be a place where we can air these discussions but not create it in a separate and unequal way to make the decision itself through the process. Why is the faculty administration, faculty decision, any less outcome-determinate than what the voters would say? I think there would be people that might disagree with your empirical assumption. Then I'm not explaining it clearly. The first, when the faculty makes the decision, Justice Kennedy, that's part of the ordinary political process. Nobody's allowed to win all the time. No one has to win all the time. No one has to lose all the time. Whatever it is, that's the ordinary political process. That's how we use the political process. The problem with mounting a racial classification within the Constitution itself is that that takes the ordinary political process to the extraordinary political process. Certainly, you could say that the whole point of something like the Equal Protection Clause is to take race off the table. Is it unreasonable for the state to say, look, race is a lightning rod? We've been told we can have affirmative action programs that do not take race into account. Socioeconomic diversity, elimination of alumni preferences, all of these things. It is very expensive whenever we have a racial classification we're immediately sued. So why don't we say we want you to do everything you can without having racial preferences. Now, if litigation determines that we're required to have racial preferences, this statute has an exception and allows them. But starting out, we want to take race off the table and try to achieve diversity without racial preferences. The problem, Your Honor, as this Court stated recently as last term in the Fisher case is that under the Equal Protection Clause, race is not all the way off the table. And the problem with proposal two is that the substance and the message that it communicates is that because of the separate and unequal political track that is created with respect to the extraordinary steps that have to be taken, the message is that even where race is being utilized as one of many factors in a constitutionally permissible way, the message that is being communicated is that all uses of race are illiterate, jibbutt, all uses of race are off the table. That race itself is a dirty word. Why doesn't the Fourth Amendment violate the rule you're saying? Why are the Fourteenth Amendment violate the rule that you're proposing? I'm a minority and I want laws that favor my minority, not just in university everywhere. My goodness, I can't have that through the normal legislative process. I have to get a constitutional amendment to do it, right? That is correct, Your Honor. Well, so I guess that on the subject of equal treatment of the races, we can eliminate racism just at the legislative level, can't we? Your Honor, the underlying basis of the entire strict scrutiny doctrine in the Fourteenth Amendment is to preclude the government, preclude the legislative and executive branch from making those determinations as absolute determinations. The Fourteenth Amendment sets the standards in their criteria by which we measure that. Of course you're correct, that's what the Fourteenth Amendment does. It sets what the rules are in terms of how race is utilized, but what the grudercase says. You can't change those rules by normal legislation. That is correct, and if you're a minority that wants favored treatment, you're just out of luck. You have to use the ordinary political process, and that's all we're saying. Constitutional amendment is not the ordinary political process. But the fact that it's a state constitutional amendment underscores my argument, which is that in order for the minority or any individual, and white minority, whatever the individual is, to say, I want the same rulebook, I want the same playing field

. Then I'm not explaining it clearly. The first, when the faculty makes the decision, Justice Kennedy, that's part of the ordinary political process. Nobody's allowed to win all the time. No one has to win all the time. No one has to lose all the time. Whatever it is, that's the ordinary political process. That's how we use the political process. The problem with mounting a racial classification within the Constitution itself is that that takes the ordinary political process to the extraordinary political process. Certainly, you could say that the whole point of something like the Equal Protection Clause is to take race off the table. Is it unreasonable for the state to say, look, race is a lightning rod? We've been told we can have affirmative action programs that do not take race into account. Socioeconomic diversity, elimination of alumni preferences, all of these things. It is very expensive whenever we have a racial classification we're immediately sued. So why don't we say we want you to do everything you can without having racial preferences. Now, if litigation determines that we're required to have racial preferences, this statute has an exception and allows them. But starting out, we want to take race off the table and try to achieve diversity without racial preferences. The problem, Your Honor, as this Court stated recently as last term in the Fisher case is that under the Equal Protection Clause, race is not all the way off the table. And the problem with proposal two is that the substance and the message that it communicates is that because of the separate and unequal political track that is created with respect to the extraordinary steps that have to be taken, the message is that even where race is being utilized as one of many factors in a constitutionally permissible way, the message that is being communicated is that all uses of race are illiterate, jibbutt, all uses of race are off the table. That race itself is a dirty word. Why doesn't the Fourth Amendment violate the rule you're saying? Why are the Fourteenth Amendment violate the rule that you're proposing? I'm a minority and I want laws that favor my minority, not just in university everywhere. My goodness, I can't have that through the normal legislative process. I have to get a constitutional amendment to do it, right? That is correct, Your Honor. Well, so I guess that on the subject of equal treatment of the races, we can eliminate racism just at the legislative level, can't we? Your Honor, the underlying basis of the entire strict scrutiny doctrine in the Fourteenth Amendment is to preclude the government, preclude the legislative and executive branch from making those determinations as absolute determinations. The Fourteenth Amendment sets the standards in their criteria by which we measure that. Of course you're correct, that's what the Fourteenth Amendment does. It sets what the rules are in terms of how race is utilized, but what the grudercase says. You can't change those rules by normal legislation. That is correct, and if you're a minority that wants favored treatment, you're just out of luck. You have to use the ordinary political process, and that's all we're saying. Constitutional amendment is not the ordinary political process. But the fact that it's a state constitutional amendment underscores my argument, which is that in order for the minority or any individual, and white minority, whatever the individual is, to say, I want the same rulebook, I want the same playing field. The problem with proposal two is that it creates two playing fields. If proposal two had been in the Michigan Constitution before any affirmative action program was adopted, would the result be the same? It would, Your Honor, because it would be building in this explicitly facial, racial classification into the state constitution. The problem are the separate and unequal systems that are being used to deal with race, and separate and unequal under the Fourteenth Amendment should come with intent and feet of race. Not a racial classification, you should not refer to it that way. It is a race. It's the prohibition of racial classification. No, Your Honor. Every prohibition of racial classification is itself a racial classification. No, Your Honor, the problem with proposal two is that it's just as in hunter. Just as in hunter. It is an explicitly facial, racial classification. It singles out race for different treatment. My goodness, this was born, this campaign started three days after Grooter itself. The author said the purpose of it was to get rid of racial preferences. If that's how you're using racial classification, I thought it meant it's directed at blacks or or Asians or no. In that sense, the Fourteenth Amendment itself is a racial classification. Well, it's the standard number. In that sense, the Fourteenth Amendment itself is a racial classification. I don't agree with that, Your Honor, because I'm measuring it's a racial classification by the Fourteenth Amendment. And that comes back to Justice Ginsburg's argument. His argument, his revisionist history of hunter, was about motive. But Your Honor, that had nothing to do with the problem in this case. When the court looked at, when the district court looked, may I finish my answer, Chief Justice Roberts? Yes. When the court looked at this particular issue, the concern was the way that it racially divided the political process itself. What he is saying is that, well, there may be all sorts of motives. That's a rational basis, and that has nothing to do with the racial classification. The definition I'm using Justice Scalia is this court's definition of a racial classification, for which all sorts trigger strict scrutiny. Thank you, Council. Mr. Driver

. The problem with proposal two is that it creates two playing fields. If proposal two had been in the Michigan Constitution before any affirmative action program was adopted, would the result be the same? It would, Your Honor, because it would be building in this explicitly facial, racial classification into the state constitution. The problem are the separate and unequal systems that are being used to deal with race, and separate and unequal under the Fourteenth Amendment should come with intent and feet of race. Not a racial classification, you should not refer to it that way. It is a race. It's the prohibition of racial classification. No, Your Honor. Every prohibition of racial classification is itself a racial classification. No, Your Honor, the problem with proposal two is that it's just as in hunter. Just as in hunter. It is an explicitly facial, racial classification. It singles out race for different treatment. My goodness, this was born, this campaign started three days after Grooter itself. The author said the purpose of it was to get rid of racial preferences. If that's how you're using racial classification, I thought it meant it's directed at blacks or or Asians or no. In that sense, the Fourteenth Amendment itself is a racial classification. Well, it's the standard number. In that sense, the Fourteenth Amendment itself is a racial classification. I don't agree with that, Your Honor, because I'm measuring it's a racial classification by the Fourteenth Amendment. And that comes back to Justice Ginsburg's argument. His argument, his revisionist history of hunter, was about motive. But Your Honor, that had nothing to do with the problem in this case. When the court looked at, when the district court looked, may I finish my answer, Chief Justice Roberts? Yes. When the court looked at this particular issue, the concern was the way that it racially divided the political process itself. What he is saying is that, well, there may be all sorts of motives. That's a rational basis, and that has nothing to do with the racial classification. The definition I'm using Justice Scalia is this court's definition of a racial classification, for which all sorts trigger strict scrutiny. Thank you, Council. Mr. Driver. Mr. Chief Justice, and may it please the court. We ask this court to uphold the Six-Sirket decision to reaffirm the doctrine that's expressed in Hunter Seattle. And to bring the Fourteenth Amendment back to its original purpose and meaning, which is to protect minority rights against a white majority, which did not occur in this case. Goodness, I thought we've held it the Fourteenth Amendment protects all races. I mean, that was the argument in the early years that it protected only only the blacks. But I thought we've rejected that. You say now that we have to proceed as though its purpose is not to protect whites, not only to protect minorities. I think it is a measure, that's an anti-discrimination measure. Right. And it's a measure in which the question of discrimination is determined, not just by power, by who has privilege in the society, and those minorities that are oppressed, be they religious, or racial need protection from a more privileged majority. And unless that exists, the Fourteenth Amendment is not violated. Is that right? So if you have a banding together of various minority groups who discriminate against whites, that's okay. I think that- Do you have any case of ours that propounds that view of the Fourteenth Amendment that it protects only minorities? Any case. No case of yours. Some people think that there is a difference between the plus and the minus. So judges differ on that point. Some agree sort of with you, and some agree sort of a not. All right. Let's think of those who agree sort of. Then I have a question. And you know this area better than I. So think of Gruder. Gruder permits affirmative action. Think of the earlier cases. They permitted affirmative action where it was to overcome the effects of past discrimination, but probably not otherwise. Now that's what I want to know. Are there areas other than education where affirmative action would not be forbidden to achieve a goal other than overcoming the effects? If you got the question, and does an answer come to mind? I think that affirmative action programs could be permissible under employment, for instance. Okay. So there are a set

. Mr. Chief Justice, and may it please the court. We ask this court to uphold the Six-Sirket decision to reaffirm the doctrine that's expressed in Hunter Seattle. And to bring the Fourteenth Amendment back to its original purpose and meaning, which is to protect minority rights against a white majority, which did not occur in this case. Goodness, I thought we've held it the Fourteenth Amendment protects all races. I mean, that was the argument in the early years that it protected only only the blacks. But I thought we've rejected that. You say now that we have to proceed as though its purpose is not to protect whites, not only to protect minorities. I think it is a measure, that's an anti-discrimination measure. Right. And it's a measure in which the question of discrimination is determined, not just by power, by who has privilege in the society, and those minorities that are oppressed, be they religious, or racial need protection from a more privileged majority. And unless that exists, the Fourteenth Amendment is not violated. Is that right? So if you have a banding together of various minority groups who discriminate against whites, that's okay. I think that- Do you have any case of ours that propounds that view of the Fourteenth Amendment that it protects only minorities? Any case. No case of yours. Some people think that there is a difference between the plus and the minus. So judges differ on that point. Some agree sort of with you, and some agree sort of a not. All right. Let's think of those who agree sort of. Then I have a question. And you know this area better than I. So think of Gruder. Gruder permits affirmative action. Think of the earlier cases. They permitted affirmative action where it was to overcome the effects of past discrimination, but probably not otherwise. Now that's what I want to know. Are there areas other than education where affirmative action would not be forbidden to achieve a goal other than overcoming the effects? If you got the question, and does an answer come to mind? I think that affirmative action programs could be permissible under employment, for instance. Okay. So there are a set. If there are a set, would I- would I like you to explain if you can take a minute? Is think of how a city is set up. There are vast number of administrators. There are a vast number of programs. It could be an administrator somewhere as he'd like to give a preference, maybe for good reason. But then the city council votes no. Or because there are other ways of doing it by first come first served or some other criteria that doesn't use race. Are all of those unlawful? Everyone, do you have to leave it up to the no matter what the subject, no matter what the- or are you going to draw a line somewhere? Is there a line that you could draw that would take your case on the right side from your point of view? But would say we're not giving power to every administrator in the city to decide on his own whether to use racial preferences without a possibility of a higher up veto. I think- I don't think you want to say but maybe you do. No, I think these are very fact-based determinations. And so somebody could make a decision that they wanted to use what you're calling racial preferences. And that couldn't mean a range of things. And that could be subject to a veto higher up. Yeah, I agree with you. So what's the line? Is there any line that you can say, look here we were trying to be very helpful. And all of a sudden they put this thing on the ballot, you can't even get it through. Okay, that's your basic point. But if you think of- you have to write something and that something has tremendous effect all over the place. So what kind of line is there in your opinion? I think Hunter Seattle provides a line. I think it says that if you have a law that has a racial focus and that law a part of proving that it has a racial focus is that it takes a benefit that eners to minorities and it removes that benefit and it restructures the political process and places a special burden on minorities to re-assertain that right. Yeah, I think that's a proper rule because- Can I come back to the question that the Chief Justice and Justice Kennedy were asking before. Essentially, they're their question. Let's say that the decision about admissions criteria across the board is basically delegated to the faculty. All right. And the faculty adopts some sort of affirmative action plan. And now that is overruled in favor of a colorblind approach at various levels going up the ladder. So maybe it's overruled by the dean of- by a dean. Maybe it's overruled by the president of the university. Maybe it's overruled by the regents. Maybe if state laws allowed it's overruled by an executive department of the state. Maybe it's overruled by the legislature through ordinary legislation

. If there are a set, would I- would I like you to explain if you can take a minute? Is think of how a city is set up. There are vast number of administrators. There are a vast number of programs. It could be an administrator somewhere as he'd like to give a preference, maybe for good reason. But then the city council votes no. Or because there are other ways of doing it by first come first served or some other criteria that doesn't use race. Are all of those unlawful? Everyone, do you have to leave it up to the no matter what the subject, no matter what the- or are you going to draw a line somewhere? Is there a line that you could draw that would take your case on the right side from your point of view? But would say we're not giving power to every administrator in the city to decide on his own whether to use racial preferences without a possibility of a higher up veto. I think- I don't think you want to say but maybe you do. No, I think these are very fact-based determinations. And so somebody could make a decision that they wanted to use what you're calling racial preferences. And that couldn't mean a range of things. And that could be subject to a veto higher up. Yeah, I agree with you. So what's the line? Is there any line that you can say, look here we were trying to be very helpful. And all of a sudden they put this thing on the ballot, you can't even get it through. Okay, that's your basic point. But if you think of- you have to write something and that something has tremendous effect all over the place. So what kind of line is there in your opinion? I think Hunter Seattle provides a line. I think it says that if you have a law that has a racial focus and that law a part of proving that it has a racial focus is that it takes a benefit that eners to minorities and it removes that benefit and it restructures the political process and places a special burden on minorities to re-assertain that right. Yeah, I think that's a proper rule because- Can I come back to the question that the Chief Justice and Justice Kennedy were asking before. Essentially, they're their question. Let's say that the decision about admissions criteria across the board is basically delegated to the faculty. All right. And the faculty adopts some sort of affirmative action plan. And now that is overruled in favor of a colorblind approach at various levels going up the ladder. So maybe it's overruled by the dean of- by a dean. Maybe it's overruled by the president of the university. Maybe it's overruled by the regents. Maybe if state laws allowed it's overruled by an executive department of the state. Maybe it's overruled by the legislature through ordinary legislation. Maybe it's overruled through a constitutional amendment. At what point does the political restructuring doctrine kick in? I think in this case the difference between what other groups can do in order to get preferential treatment for their sons and daughters and what racial minorities are subject to, the level of distinction places such a high burden on my colleagues. Well, that really isn't responsive to my question. Let's say exactly what was done here is done at all of these levels. At what point does the doctrine kick in? When it goes from the faculty to the dean, from the dean to the president, etc., etc. Where does this apply? I think it depends on where it is that minorities face a heavier and special purpose. It can't be that because the normal political process imposes burdens on different groups. I thought the line was very simple one, which is if the normal academic decision making is in the dean, the faculty at whatever level as long as the normal right to control is being exercised, then that person could change the decision. So if they delegate most admissions decisions as I understand from the record to the faculty, but they still regularly, besides race, veto some of those decisions and race is now one of them, then the Board of Regents can do that normally. So could the president, if that's the way it's normally done? It's when the process's political processes change specifically and only for race, as a constitutional amendment here was intended to do that the political doctrine is violated. Have I restated? You have. You've restated it very well and I agree with you. I still don't understand your answer to Justice Elitos' question. Suppose the dean has authority in the bylaws of the university to reverse what the faculty does, but you have a dean who just does not like affirmative action. He's dead against it and he makes the decision to reverse the faculty. Do you have a remedy? I don't think Hunter Seattle applies. You have Justice Elitos of course, then it's the president of the university. Then it's the legislature. I think you need two things. I think you need the decision making, the decision making body. If the University of Michigan Regents decided tomorrow to eliminate affirmative action programs and there was no prop too, they have the legal right to do that. They are the decision making body and minorities still could go and lobby the regents, still could go and talk about the questions of racial and ethnicities. Would that be true if they had never gotten involved in admissions criteria before? They had the authority, but they left that to the university officials. I think if they have the plenary authority to do that, yeah, I think that again, if they wanted to eliminate affirmative action programs and they had that plenary authority and it was guaranteed by the Michigan State Constitution. It had existed for 150 years and they chose to enter this area. I think that's how that is consistent with just as so to my or his answer to my question. Don't the people of Michigan have, don't the people of Michigan have plenary authority? In this case, the particular, it's, they're applying that plenary authority in or in in a way that is racially focused and creates a political process that is disadvantageous to my. About saying instead of political process, don't let me put words in your mouth. I think what you think here

. Maybe it's overruled through a constitutional amendment. At what point does the political restructuring doctrine kick in? I think in this case the difference between what other groups can do in order to get preferential treatment for their sons and daughters and what racial minorities are subject to, the level of distinction places such a high burden on my colleagues. Well, that really isn't responsive to my question. Let's say exactly what was done here is done at all of these levels. At what point does the doctrine kick in? When it goes from the faculty to the dean, from the dean to the president, etc., etc. Where does this apply? I think it depends on where it is that minorities face a heavier and special purpose. It can't be that because the normal political process imposes burdens on different groups. I thought the line was very simple one, which is if the normal academic decision making is in the dean, the faculty at whatever level as long as the normal right to control is being exercised, then that person could change the decision. So if they delegate most admissions decisions as I understand from the record to the faculty, but they still regularly, besides race, veto some of those decisions and race is now one of them, then the Board of Regents can do that normally. So could the president, if that's the way it's normally done? It's when the process's political processes change specifically and only for race, as a constitutional amendment here was intended to do that the political doctrine is violated. Have I restated? You have. You've restated it very well and I agree with you. I still don't understand your answer to Justice Elitos' question. Suppose the dean has authority in the bylaws of the university to reverse what the faculty does, but you have a dean who just does not like affirmative action. He's dead against it and he makes the decision to reverse the faculty. Do you have a remedy? I don't think Hunter Seattle applies. You have Justice Elitos of course, then it's the president of the university. Then it's the legislature. I think you need two things. I think you need the decision making, the decision making body. If the University of Michigan Regents decided tomorrow to eliminate affirmative action programs and there was no prop too, they have the legal right to do that. They are the decision making body and minorities still could go and lobby the regents, still could go and talk about the questions of racial and ethnicities. Would that be true if they had never gotten involved in admissions criteria before? They had the authority, but they left that to the university officials. I think if they have the plenary authority to do that, yeah, I think that again, if they wanted to eliminate affirmative action programs and they had that plenary authority and it was guaranteed by the Michigan State Constitution. It had existed for 150 years and they chose to enter this area. I think that's how that is consistent with just as so to my or his answer to my question. Don't the people of Michigan have, don't the people of Michigan have plenary authority? In this case, the particular, it's, they're applying that plenary authority in or in in a way that is racially focused and creates a political process that is disadvantageous to my. About saying instead of political process, don't let me put words in your mouth. I think what you think here. You say we're the authority was divided in a certain way and that's true under the constitution of the state. So the state government lacks the power. And then you have to take the power from the people and change the constitution. And when you do that in respect to a benefit, then in respect to benefits, Washington, you know, Seattle and Hunter kick in. So you're not dealing with past discrimination. Well, this is this what we're talking about in terms of affirmative action are constitutionally permissible programs that were shown to this court to be the only way to achieve racial diversity and integration at the University of Michigan. And whether you, whether you explain that by looking at the reality of the inequality in education for black and white Michigan or whatever it is that you come up with that requires that the university has shown that this is the only way to achieve diversity in which racial diversity is a part of the, is a part of the quotient. And so to take away that right from the University and from the regions. And I just want to go back to one of the questions that was answered. If you look at the law schools, the medical schools, the professional schools now in the state of Michigan, there's been a precipitous drop in underrepresented minority enrollment in those schools. We are going back to the re-sigregation of those schools because of the elimination of affirmative action. To what extent does your argument depend? And I thought both Hunter and Seattle speak in these terms that the policies that are more difficult to enact are beneficial for the minority group. The, say that I'm sorry, I can't. But what extent does your argument depend upon the assumption that the programs that you say are now more difficult to enact are beneficial to the minority group? I think it's an important component part because I think it's in the benefit to the minority group that it's especially important that the political process be on a level field. Right. What if the question of whether it's a benefit to the minority group is more open to debate? Whether it's through the mismatch theory that Taylor and Sander I guess have adopted or other theories. Do we have to assume in your favor that these definitely are beneficial to particular minority groups? Certainly the minority voters of Michigan believe them to be because 90% of black voters in Michigan voted against Prop 2. And I think that that's a clear indication of the popularity of these programs and the perceived benefit of the progress. There's a difference. There may be a difference between popularity and benefit. In other words, you want us to assume that the programs are beneficial to the minority group. Yes. And they are beneficial to minority groups. They may serve to provide benefits for the population beyond minority groups, but they are benefit if they- Your opponent says otherwise. He says that minority students have taken tougher courses. They have been better qualified to be admitted and all sorts of other benefits. So, you know, it's certainly a debatable question. It's a debatable question in another forum in a different case. And in fact, I think that case was the grutter case. This case isn't about- Isn't just about whether or not affirmative action benefits minorities

. You say we're the authority was divided in a certain way and that's true under the constitution of the state. So the state government lacks the power. And then you have to take the power from the people and change the constitution. And when you do that in respect to a benefit, then in respect to benefits, Washington, you know, Seattle and Hunter kick in. So you're not dealing with past discrimination. Well, this is this what we're talking about in terms of affirmative action are constitutionally permissible programs that were shown to this court to be the only way to achieve racial diversity and integration at the University of Michigan. And whether you, whether you explain that by looking at the reality of the inequality in education for black and white Michigan or whatever it is that you come up with that requires that the university has shown that this is the only way to achieve diversity in which racial diversity is a part of the, is a part of the quotient. And so to take away that right from the University and from the regions. And I just want to go back to one of the questions that was answered. If you look at the law schools, the medical schools, the professional schools now in the state of Michigan, there's been a precipitous drop in underrepresented minority enrollment in those schools. We are going back to the re-sigregation of those schools because of the elimination of affirmative action. To what extent does your argument depend? And I thought both Hunter and Seattle speak in these terms that the policies that are more difficult to enact are beneficial for the minority group. The, say that I'm sorry, I can't. But what extent does your argument depend upon the assumption that the programs that you say are now more difficult to enact are beneficial to the minority group? I think it's an important component part because I think it's in the benefit to the minority group that it's especially important that the political process be on a level field. Right. What if the question of whether it's a benefit to the minority group is more open to debate? Whether it's through the mismatch theory that Taylor and Sander I guess have adopted or other theories. Do we have to assume in your favor that these definitely are beneficial to particular minority groups? Certainly the minority voters of Michigan believe them to be because 90% of black voters in Michigan voted against Prop 2. And I think that that's a clear indication of the popularity of these programs and the perceived benefit of the progress. There's a difference. There may be a difference between popularity and benefit. In other words, you want us to assume that the programs are beneficial to the minority group. Yes. And they are beneficial to minority groups. They may serve to provide benefits for the population beyond minority groups, but they are benefit if they- Your opponent says otherwise. He says that minority students have taken tougher courses. They have been better qualified to be admitted and all sorts of other benefits. So, you know, it's certainly a debatable question. It's a debatable question in another forum in a different case. And in fact, I think that case was the grutter case. This case isn't about- Isn't just about whether or not affirmative action benefits minorities. It's also the restructuring of the political process and the special burden that's placed on minorities. It's not- If you want to go back to debating the, you know, whether or not- The change in your answer then, your answer to the chief was it does depend upon whether it benefits minorities. Now you're saying it doesn't depend on whether it benefits minorities at all. It's just whether it places a greater burden on minorities to change it. Which is it? One or the other. I think it's a two-part test. I think the first- The first thing that you look at is, is there a racial focus to the law and is the benefit that has been taken away something that it eners two minorities? And I think the second part of the test, and that's why I think Seattle Hunter is such a narrow doctrine, is whether there also has been a restructuring of the political process and a special burden placed on minorities. It requires both. Thank you, counsel. Mr. Bush, you have four minutes remaining. Thank you, Mr. Chief Justice. I'm going to start with a sentence from Crawford, decided the same day as Seattle where this court defined what a racial classification is. A race of classification either says or implies that persons are to be treated differently on a count of race. It doesn't say anything about laws with or without a racial focus. And we think that's the test that ultimately should come out of the decision in this case. Now my friends on the other side disagree with that because if that's the test, section 26 is constitutional. And so they draw this false dichotomy between laws that involve race and laws that don't involve race. We'll put them in two separate chambers of the legislature and charge a fee if you want to talk about race. And we know that can't be right because of Chief Justice Roberts, your observation, that the whole point of equal protection is to take race off the table when everyone is being treated the same. That's why they- You quoted from Crawford. Yes. There is an opposing quote in Seattle itself on page 46. Yes. When the State's allocation of power places unusual burdens on the ability of racial groups to enact legislation designed to overcome the special condition of prejudice, the governmental action seriously curtails the operation of those political processes ordinarily to be lied on to protect minorities and it quotes the Chirilin products. So, and then the following sentence is in the most direct sense, this implicates the judiciary's special role, not of treating individuals as individuals, but the judiciary special role in safeguarding the interests of those groups that are relegated to a position of political powerlessness. So the rationale of Seattle is that notion that you can't put hurdles in the way of a disadvantaged minority. Justice Ginsburg, there's two problems with that. First, that's where the respondents theory most closely knocks up against Gruder because you're right

. It's also the restructuring of the political process and the special burden that's placed on minorities. It's not- If you want to go back to debating the, you know, whether or not- The change in your answer then, your answer to the chief was it does depend upon whether it benefits minorities. Now you're saying it doesn't depend on whether it benefits minorities at all. It's just whether it places a greater burden on minorities to change it. Which is it? One or the other. I think it's a two-part test. I think the first- The first thing that you look at is, is there a racial focus to the law and is the benefit that has been taken away something that it eners two minorities? And I think the second part of the test, and that's why I think Seattle Hunter is such a narrow doctrine, is whether there also has been a restructuring of the political process and a special burden placed on minorities. It requires both. Thank you, counsel. Mr. Bush, you have four minutes remaining. Thank you, Mr. Chief Justice. I'm going to start with a sentence from Crawford, decided the same day as Seattle where this court defined what a racial classification is. A race of classification either says or implies that persons are to be treated differently on a count of race. It doesn't say anything about laws with or without a racial focus. And we think that's the test that ultimately should come out of the decision in this case. Now my friends on the other side disagree with that because if that's the test, section 26 is constitutional. And so they draw this false dichotomy between laws that involve race and laws that don't involve race. We'll put them in two separate chambers of the legislature and charge a fee if you want to talk about race. And we know that can't be right because of Chief Justice Roberts, your observation, that the whole point of equal protection is to take race off the table when everyone is being treated the same. That's why they- You quoted from Crawford. Yes. There is an opposing quote in Seattle itself on page 46. Yes. When the State's allocation of power places unusual burdens on the ability of racial groups to enact legislation designed to overcome the special condition of prejudice, the governmental action seriously curtails the operation of those political processes ordinarily to be lied on to protect minorities and it quotes the Chirilin products. So, and then the following sentence is in the most direct sense, this implicates the judiciary's special role, not of treating individuals as individuals, but the judiciary special role in safeguarding the interests of those groups that are relegated to a position of political powerlessness. So the rationale of Seattle is that notion that you can't put hurdles in the way of a disadvantaged minority. Justice Ginsburg, there's two problems with that. First, that's where the respondents theory most closely knocks up against Gruder because you're right. Under Seattle and Hunter, you've got to have a policy designed for the purpose of primarily benefiting the minority. But if that's the policy, it violates Gruder, which is supposed to benefit everyone. But the bigger problem is if you treat diversity as a way, or when you take away a tool for diversity, that's what Seattle is saying is wrong. Right, but the bigger problem is that you can't take the tool away simply because it may include race as a factor simply because you're changing the playing field. But Justice Sonoma, the biggest problem with respondents tests with applying the literal language of Seattle is that, as I said, the Federal Fair Housing Act, the Equal Credit Act, a State Equal Protection Law that mentions race, all of these things fall in the category of laws dealing with race. Some are discriminatory. In this case, both involve constitutional amendments. So why can't the law be drawn, the line be drawn there? If you change the allocation of power in one of these less substantial ways, that's one thing. But when you require constitutional amendments, that's really a big deal. Because that would still invalidate the Michigan Equal Protection Laws, which has a racial focus. It says you cannot discriminate based on race or sex. And yet no one would argue, should be subject to scrutiny. But that is the why your sentence for a treaty. That's the benefit minority group. What I'm thinking is, go read. The cases, you yourself seem to say, these cases seem to apply alike to the benefits or to the discrimination against it. I mean, there's lots of language in Seattle. Right. Take that and say, all right, it was meant in context. But the context includes constitutional amendments. Because with the constitutional amendment, you are restructuring. Now you'd lose on that theory. But there would be a limitation on the extent to which the people have the right to move powers around. Justice Breyer, the limitation has to be not only that, but also that you're repealing an anti-discrimination law, not an equal treatment law, or again, otherwise the state equal protection clause has to fall. So to the extent that I'm right, that's a way that you can narrow hunter in Seattle and section 26 has to survive. If I'm wrong about that, then respectfully, Seattle and Hunter should be overruled. Either way, it does not violate equal protection to require equal treatment. Thank you. Thank you, Council. The case is submitted